Los valores como recursos epistémicos en las críticas feministas de la ciencia

  1. González García, Marta I. 1
  1. 1 Universidad de Oviedo
    info

    Universidad de Oviedo

    Oviedo, España

    ROR https://ror.org/006gksa02

Revista:
Scio

ISSN: 1887-9853

Año de publicación: 2022

Título del ejemplar: Pensamiento crítico

Número: 22

Páginas: 235-263

Tipo: Artículo

DOI: 10.46583/SCIO_2022.22.1012 DIALNET GOOGLE SCHOLAR lock_openDialnet editor

Otras publicaciones en: Scio

Resumen

En este trabajo se analizan las aportaciones de las críticas feministas para el debate actual sobre el papel de los valores no epistémicos en la ciencia. La revitalización de la discusión sobre los valores y la responsabilidad social de la ciencia en las últimas décadas responde a preocupaciones como la crisis de la replicabilidad, la creciente comercialización o el papel de la ciencia para la política. En todas ellas la influencia de valores de carácter no epistémico aparece como problemática. La crítica feminista, no obstante, proporciona ejemplos del funcionamiento de los valores políticos como recursos para una crítica constructiva que, acompañada de reflexividad y capacidad de autocorrección por parte de las comunidades implicadas, puede promover los propios objetivos epistémicos de la ciencia. Utilizaré dos ejemplos bien conocidos, la primatología y la neurociencia cognitiva, para discutir la interacción de lo epistémico y lo no epistémico en las críticas feministas. Los casos analizados servirán también para explorar la propia interacción de valores en la recepción de las críticas y para introducir la discusión sobre el denominado “nuevo problema de la demarcación”.

Referencias bibliográficas

  • Almassi, B. (2019). Beyond Science Wars Redux: Feminist Philosophy of Science as Trustworthy Science Criticism. Hypatia, 34(4), 858-868. doi:10.1111/hypa.12500
  • Altmann, J. (1974). Observational Study of Behavior: Sampling Methods. Behaviour, 49(3/4), pp. 227-267.
  • Anderson, E. (1995). Knowledge, Human Interests, and Objectivity in Feminist Epistemology, Philosophical Topics, 23(2), 27-58.
  • Anderson, E. (2004). Uses of Value Judgments in Science: A General Argument, with Lessons from a Case Study of Feminist Research on Divorce. Hypatia, 19(1), 1-24. doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2004.tb01266.x
  • Anderson, E. (2020). Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, En E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition). [[[https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/feminism-epistemology/]]]
  • Antony L.M. (1993). Quine as Feminist. En L.M. Antony y C. Witt (Eds.), A Mind of One’s Own (pp. 185–225). Westview Press.
  • Andreoletti, M. (2021). Replicability Crisis and Scientific Reforms: Overlooked Issues and Unmet Challenges, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 33(3), 135-151. doi:10.1080/02698595.2021.1943292
  • Bluhm, R. (2016). Values and Evidence in Feminist Philosophy and in Neuroscience. En M.C. Amoretti y N. Vasallo (Eds.), Meta-Philosophical Reflection on Feminist Philosophies of Science (pp. 91-111). Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 317. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-26348-9_6
  • Bluhm, R. (2021). Neurosexism and our understanding of sex differences in the brain. En S. Crasnow y K. Intemann (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Feminist Philosophy of Science (pp. 316-327). Routledge.
  • Brigandt, I. (2015). Social values influence the adequacy conditions of scientific theories: beyond inductive risk. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45(3), 326–356. doi:10.1080/00455091.2015.1079004
  • Botero, M. (2021). Observing Primates. Gender, Power, and Knowledge in Primatology, En S. Crasnow y K. Intemann (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Feminist Philosophy of Science (pp. 275-288). Routledge.
  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. University of Pittsburgh Press.
  • Douglas H. (2016). Values in science. En P. Humphreys (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Science (pp. 609-630). Oxford University Press.
  • Eliot, L., Ahmed, A., Khan, H. y Patel, J. (2021). Dump the ‘dimorphism’: Comprehensive synthesis of human brain studies reveals few male-female differences beyond size. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 125, pp. 667-697.
  • Elliott, K.C. y Steel, D. (Eds.) (2017). Current Controversies in Values and Science. Routledge.
  • Farrell, K.N. (2020). Untrol: Post-Truth and the New Normal of Post-Normal Science, Social Epistemology, 34(4), 330-345. doi:10.1080/02691728.2019.17061172005.
  • Fedigan, L.M. (2001). The Paradox of Feminist Primatology: The Goddess’s Discipline? En A.N.H. Creuger, E. Lurbekc y L. Schiebinger (Eds.), Feminism in Twentieth Century Science, Technology and Medicine (pp. 46-72). University of Chicago Press.
  • Fedigan, L.M. (2005). Primatology is an equal-opportunity science. En C.L. Biggs y P.J. Downe (Eds.), Gendered Intersections: An Introduction to Women's and Gender Studies (pp. 362-366). Fernwood Publishing,
  • Fee, E. (1979). Nineteenth-Century Craniology: The study of the female skull. Bulletin of the History of Medicine, 53(3), 415-433.
  • Fernández Pinto, M. (2015). Tensions in agnotology: Normativity in the studies of commercially driven ignorance. Social Studies of Science, 45(2), 294-315.
  • Fine, C. (2010). Delusions of Gender: How Our Minds, Society, and Neurosexism Create Difference. Norton.
  • Fine, C. (2013). Is There Sexism in Functional Neuroimaging Investigations of Sex Differences? Neuroethics, 6(2), 369–409.
  • Fine, C. (2021). Fairly Criticized, or Politicized? Conflicts in the Neuroscience of Sex Differences in the Human Brain. Cold Spring Harbor Perspectives in Biology. doi:10.1101/cshperspect.a039115
  • Freese, J. y D. Peterson (2018). The Emergence of Statistical Objectivity: Changing Ideas of Epistemic Vice and Virtue in Science. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 36(3), 289-313. doi:10.1177/0735275118794987
  • Funtowicz, S. y Ravetz, J. (1993). Science for the post-normal age. Futures, 25(7), 739-755.
  • García-Sifuentes, Y. y Maney, D. (2021), Reporting and misreporting of sex differences in the biological sciences. eLife. doi:10.7554/eLife.70817
  • González García, M.I. (2006). Epistemología feminista y práctica científica. En N. Blázquez y J. Flores (Eds.), Ciencia, Tecnología y Género en Iberoamérica (pp. 575-596). Centro de Investigaciones Interdisciplinares en Ciencias y Humanidades, UNAM.
  • Haraway, D. (1984). Primatology is Politics by Other Means. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1984, 2, 489-524.
  • Haraway, D. (1989). Primate Visions. Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern Science. Routledge.
  • Intemann, K. (2010). 25 Years of Feminist Empiricism and Standpoint Theory: Where Are We Now? Hypatia, 25(4), 778-796. doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2010.01138.x
  • Intemann, K. (2017). Feminism, Values, and the Bias Paradox: Why Value Management is not Sufficient. En K.C. Elliott y D. Steel (Eds.), Current Controversies in Values and Science (pp. 130-144). Routledge.
  • Intemann, K. (2021). Feminist Perspectives on Values in Science. En S. Crasnow y K. Intemann (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Feminist Philosophy of Science (pp. 201-215). Routledge.
  • Joel, D., Berman, Z., Tavor, I., Wexler, N., Gaber, O., Stein, Y., et al. (2015). Sex beyond the Genitalia: The Human Brain Mosaic. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 112 (50), 15468-15473. doi:10.1073/pnas.1509654112
  • Joel, D. y McCarthy, M. (2017). Incorporating Sex as a Biological Variable in Neuropsychiatric Research: Where Are We Now and Where Should We Be? Neuropsychopharmacology, 42(2), 379-385. doi: 10.1038/npp.2016.79
  • Jordan-Young, R.M. (2010). Brain storm: The flaws in the science of sex difference. Harvard University Press.
  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The Advancement of Science. Oxford University Press.
  • Kourany, J. (2010). Philosophy of Science after Feminism. Oxford University Press.
  • Koskinen I. y Rolin K. (2021). Distinguishing between legitimate and illegitimate roles for values in transdisciplinary research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 91(1), 191-198. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsa.2021.12.001.
  • Langlitz, N. y Strum, S. (2017). Baboons and the Origins of Actor-Network Theory. BioSocieties, 12(1), 158-167. doi:10.1057/s41292-016-0035-y
  • Latour, B. (2004). Why has critique run out of steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern. Critical Inquiry, 30(2). doi:10.1086/421123
  • Lee, S.K. (2018). Sex as important biological variable in biomedical research. BMB Reports, 51(4), pp. 167-173. doi:10.5483/BMBRep.2018.51.4.034
  • Legg, T., Hatchard, J., Gilmore, A.B. (2021). The Science for Profit Model—How and why corporations influence science and the use of science in policy and practice. PLoS ONE, 16(6), e0253272. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0253272
  • Lloyd, E. A. (1995). Objectivity and the Double Standard for Feminist Epistemologies. Synthese, 104(3), 351–381.
  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton University Press.
  • Longino, H.E. (2002), The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton University Press.
  • Longino, H. (2019). The Social Dimensions of Scientific Knowledge. En E.N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 Edition). [[[https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/scientific-knowledge-social/]]]
  • Lynch, M. (2020). We Have Never Been Anti-Science: Reflections on Science Wars and Post-Truth. Engaging Science, Technology and Society, 6, 49-57. doi:10.17351/ests2020.309
  • Maney, D. (2016). Perils and pitfalls of reporting sex differences. Philosophical Transactions of The Royal Society B, 371(1688). doi:10.1098/rstb.2015.0119
  • McCarthy, M.M. (2011). Reframing Sexual Differentiation of the Brain. Nature Neuroscience, 14(6), 677-683. doi:10.1038/nn.2834
  • McMullin, E. (1983). Values in Science. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1982, 3–28.
  • Michaels, D. (2008). Doubt is their product: how industry's assault on science threatens your health. Oxford University Press.
  • Nelson, L.H. (1990). From Quine to Feminist Empiricism. Temple University Press.
  • Nelson, L.H. (2017). Biology and Feminism. A Philosophical Introduction. Cambridge University Press.
  • Oreskes, N. y Conway, E.M. (2010). Merchants of Doubt. Bloombury Press.
  • Pérez Sedeño, E. y García Dauder, S. (2018). Las mentiras científicas sobre las mujeres. La Catarata.
  • Persson, S. y Pownall, M. (2021). Can Open Science be a Tool to Dismantle Claims of Hardwired Brain Sex Differences? Opportunities and Challenges for Feminist Researchers. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 45(4), 493-504. doi:10.1177/03616843211037613
  • Pinnick, C.L. (1994). Feminist Epistemology: Implications for Philosophy of Science. Philosophy of Science, 61(4), 646–657. doi:10.1086/289827
  • Proctor, R. y Schiebinger, L. (Eds.) (2008). Agnotology: The Making and Unmaking of Ignorance. Stanford University Press.
  • Resnik (2007). The Price of Truth. How Money Affects the Norms of Science. Oxford University Press.
  • Reverter, S. (2017). El neurofeminismo frente a la investigación sobre la diferencia sexual. Daimon. Revista Internacional de Filosofía, 95–110. doi:10.6018/daimon/291561
  • Richardson, S. (2021). Sex contextualism. Philosophy, Theory & Practice in Biology, 13(9). doi:10.3998/ptpbio.16039257.0013.009
  • Rippon, G., Jordan-Young, R., Kaiser, A., Joel, D. y Fine, C. (2017). Journal of Neuroscience Research Policy on Addressing Sex as a Biological Variable: Comments, Clarifications, and Elaborations. Journal of Neuroscience Research, 95 (7), 1357-1359. doi:10.1002/jnr.24045.
  • Rippon, G., Eliot, L., Genon, S., Joel, D. (2021). How hype and hyperbole distort the neuroscience of sex differences. PLoS Biology 19(5): e3001253. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.3001253
  • Rolin, K. (2002). Is 'science as social' a feminist insight? Social Epistemology, 16(3), 233-249. doi:10.1080/0269172022000025606
  • Rowell, T. (2000). A few peculiar primates. En S. Strum y L. Fedigan (Eds.). Primate Encounters (pp. 57-70). The University of Chicago Press.
  • Schrouff, J., Pischedda, D., Genon, S., Fryns, G., Pinho, A. L., Vassena, E., Liuzzi, A.G. y Ferrira, F.S. (2019). Gender bias in (neuro)science: Facts, consequences, and solutions. European Journal of Neuroscience, 50(7), 3094-3100. doi:10.1111/ejn.14397
  • Schmitz, S. y Höppner, G. (2014). Neurofeminism and feminist neurosciences: a critical review of contemporary brain research. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8(546). https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00546
  • Siegel, J.A., Calogero, R.M., Eaton, A.A. y Roberts, T.A. (2021). Identifying Gaps and Building Bridges Between Feminist Psychology and Open Science. Psychology of Woman Quarterly, 45(4), pp. 407-411. doi:10.1177/03616843211044494
  • Solís, C. (1994). Razones e intereses: la historia de la ciencia después de Kuhn. Paidós.
  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social Empiricism. MIT Press.
  • Solomon, M. (2012). Socially Responsible Science and the Unity of Values. Perspectives on Science, 20(3), 331-338.
  • Strum, S. (1987). Almost Human: A Journey into the World of Baboons. Random House.
  • Strum, S.C. y L.M. Fedigan (eds.) (2000). Primate Encounters. Models of Science, Gender, and Society. University of Chicago Press.
  • Tang-Martínez, Z. (2020). The history and impact of women in animal behaviour and the ABS: A North American Perspective. Animal Behaviour, 164, pp. 251-260.
  • Toole, B. (2020). Demarginalizing Standpoint Epistemology. Episteme, 1-19. doi:10-1017/epi.2020.8